Reflective Commentary (2025)

On reflection, writing this essay was both a rigorous and rewarding endeavour. My intention was to break down Kant’s dense definition of ‘fine art’ into manageable parts in order to make sense of his philosophy for myself and, hopefully, for my readers. I approached this by carefully examining each element of Kant’s statement, supplementing my analysis with references from theology, cultural criticism, and the sociology of knowledge. At the time, I believed that these interdisciplinary connections would enrich my discussion of Kant and help situate his ideas in a wider intellectual context.

With hindsight, I can see that the essay’s structure, while helpful for clarity, led to a certain amount of repetition. My desire to be thorough sometimes meant restating points rather than developing them further or offering fresh insight. I was also eager to bring my Christian perspective into the discourse, having always been interested in how faith might interact with philosophical concepts. However, I recognise now that these theological digressions, while heartfelt, might have diverted attention from a more sustained focus on Kant himself. Moreover, my discussion of the necessity of the fine arts category rather echoed Kant’s logic rather than offering a deeper critique or exploration of alternative aesthetic theories.

If I had the opportunity to rewrite the essay now, I would strive for greater conciseness and depth in my analysis. I would also aim to compare Kant with other philosophers, such as Hegel or later aesthetic thinkers, in a more systematic way. In addition, I am more aware these days of the importance of engaging critically with Western-centric assumptions in definitions of art, and I would seek to address that as well.

Nonetheless, writing this essay was valuable for helping me develop both my understanding of Kant and my academic voice. I still appreciate how it encouraged me to see the connections between philosophy, culture, and theology. These are connections I continue to explore and refine in my later work.

The Intrinsic Purposiveness of Fine Art: Kant on Mind, Genius, and Social Communication

Definition of “Fine Arts”

Immanuel Kant defines fine art as “a mode of representation which is intrinsically purposive, and which, although devoid of an end, has the effect of advancing the culture of the mental powers in the interest of social communication.”[1]  By deconstructing[1] [2]  his definition we gain a clearer insight into the genius of Kant’s creation. 

(1) Fine art is a conduit of expression (“a mode of representation”).  Mode of representation is a vehicle for the portrayal of art.  Art interpreted as a specific form (“fine”) in which function (“art”) resides.  With this definition Kant begins to place art in context.  We are not here considering art generally but fine art specifically.  Fine art is a method of communication.  Fine art is a pathway for portrayal of a person, persona, or topic originating in the mind of the author.  Later, Kant refers to this imaginative author as genius.

(2) Fine art possesses innate purpose (“which is intrinsically purposive”).  Intrinsic purpose is the essence of fine art.  Fine art is born through the mind of genius in the form of creative expression.  That which is Intrinsic[3] [4]  is woven into the fabric of an idea.  Think of an ornate tapestry in which artwork is fashioned by warp and woof making up the fabric.  Warp is the thread drawn lengthwise through the transverse woof thread to create cloth.   Intrinsic purpose is to art what thread is to tapestry.  Intrinsically purposive reflection is the essential nature of fine art.

(3) Fine art is “devoid of an end.”  Thus, fine art is entirely lacking in practical function.  Art is an aesthetic experience.  Here art is limited to artistic or aesthetic purpose.  Fine art must be discerned to be art and not nature.  Notwithstanding the finality in its form[5] [6] , fine art must have the appearance of being free from the restriction of groundless rules as if it were a product of ordinary nature.  Accordingly the end product of fine art, deliberate though it be, must not have the appearance of being purposeful; i.e., fine art must be clothed with the robe of nature, although recognized to be art.

(4) Fine art advances the “culture of the mental powers.”  Kant provides his own commentary as follows:

For the beautiful must not be judged according to concepts, but by the purposive manner in which the imagination is attuned so as to accord with the faculty of concepts generally; and so rule and precept are incapable of serving as the requisite subjective standard for that aesthetic and unconditional purposiveness in fine art which has to make a warranted claim to be bound to please everyone.[2] 

Christopher Dawson wrote of culture, “A social culture is an organized way of life which is based on a common tradition and conditioned by a common environment.”[3] Further, “culture is the form of society.  The society without culture is a formless society….”[4]  He adds, “Our whole social environment seems to us to be filled with forces which really exist only in our own minds.”

Kant’s mention of “mental powers” harkens to the essence of existence.  Man exists in the physical.  Man exists in the mind[7] [8] .   The life of the mind is the distinctive of man from all else in the ordered world.  The idea of “vivere viventibus est esse, that is, the very being of living things is that such things do live.”[5]  When Aristotle defined the mind as “that power that is capable of knowing all things” he enlisted the knowing capacity of man.[6]  Dorothy Sayers concluded, “For the sole true end of education is simply this: to teach men how to learn for themselves….”[7]

Contextually, Kant proposes that fine art has the “effect of advancing the culture of the mental powers.”  My interpretation is that fine art is a cultural norm in and of its own right.  There is a culture of the fine arts.  This cultural milieu has the impact of advancing the mind of man (“mental powers”).  Fine arts stimulates the mind of man to the imaginative.  A genius creates the fine art that is imparted to another who interprets the fine art product thus advancing the mental powers.  This idea of advancing the mental powers is a strong advocate for the life of the mind, even in a classical sense.  Fine art is the apex of all arts existing in the most imaginative place in the mind of man.

(5) Fine art is that which is “in the interest of social communication.”  The concept of social has been developed through many years as the sociology of knowledge.  Reality is a social construct.  Sociology of knowledge addresses the processes in which this occurs.  The pertinent terms are “reality” and “knowledge.”  These terms have “a long history of philosophical inquiry.”[8]  Man interfaces with man.  This is social.  This creates culture.  Fine art is in the best interest of the advancing of man in a social context.

(6) Fine art has multiple agendas (“and which”) converging into imaginative expression of genius.  Fine art is not a one dimensional expression rather includes intrinsic purpose, lacks end, advances the culture of mental powers, and is in the interest of social communication.

Kant begins his discussion of “Fine Art” by saying, “There is no science of the beautiful, but only a critique. Nor, again, is there such a thing as beautiful science, but only beautiful art.”[9]  This simple yet insightful approach succinctly packages the fundamental idea proposed by Kant.  Neither science of the beautiful nor beautiful science exists as science requires “reasons and proofs.”[10] Science fails “to be a judgement of taste.”[11]  To define the study of the beautiful as a scientific (“science of the beautiful”) endeavor is a contradiction especially by the standards established by Kant.  Further, to define science as beautiful (“beautiful science”) is to impose on science (a proof oriented discipline) a definition from a non-proof based idea (beauty).  

Fine art in the “fulness of its perfection” requires a “large store of knowledge” of language, literature, history, and classical learning.  These “historical sciences in turn “form the necessary preparation and groundwork for fine art….”[12]  Seeing the beautiful as beautiful is not founded in rudimentary scientific reasoning since there are no arbitrary rules forming the beautiful.

Fine art is “free from the restraint of arbitrary rules.”[13]  The product of fine art must be “recognized to be art and not nature.”[14]  Art is the product of imagination while nature is not a result of man’s imagination.  The universal idea of art that is recognized to be “beautiful which pleases in the mere judgement of it…” rather than mechanical art where judgement is based upon a sensation or concept.

To define “fine art” Kant introduces the idea of genius.  The genius of fine art is an innate talent or natural endowment.  He concludes, “Genius is the innate mental aptitude (ingenium) through which nature gives the rule to art.”[15]  When an author owes his product to genius “he does not know how the ideas for it have entered into his head, nor has he it in his power to invent the like at pleasure, or methodically, and communicate the same to others in such precepts as would enable them to produce similar products.”[16]

Kant concludes that “everyone is agreed on the point of the complete opposition between genius and the spirit of imitation.  “Now since learning is nothing but imitation, the greatest ability, or aptness as a pupil (capacity, is still, as such, not equivalent to genius).”[17]  Even if an individual coalesced the greatest minds available to his thinking capacity this does not make him a genius.  “For what is accomplished in this way is something that could have been learned.”[18]  Accordingly, all that Newton “set forth in his immortal work” can be learned.[19]  Kant offers this thoughts:

The reason is that all the steps that Newton had to take from the first elements of geometry to his greatest and most profound discoveries were such as he could make intuitively evident and plain to follow, not only for himself but for everyone else.[20]

However, when considering Homer one can “show how his ideas, so rich at once in fantasy and in thought, enter and assemble themselves in his brain, for the good reason that he does not himself know, and so cannot teach others.”[21]

Of the imaginative art Kant concludes, “Genius can do no more than furnish rich material for products of fine art; its elaboration and its form require a talent academically trained, so that it may be employed in such a way as to stand the test of judgement.”  Of judgement of the fine arts Kant states, “For judging beautiful objects, as such, what is required is taste; but for fine art, i.e., the production of such objects, one needs genius.”[22]  Of the beautiful he concludes, “A beauty of nature is a beautiful thing; beauty of art is a beautiful representation of a thing.”[23]

Address Some of the Issues or Problems with Creating this Separate Category of Arts

Aesthetic qualities require a perception for and a refined judgment in good taste.  This quality separates fine art from the more popular art of modern society.  This definition continues to evolve as society presses on toward a postmodern era dominated by secular age thought.  Fine in this context is not a judgment of the quality of the artwork rather the assertions of a university discipline[9]  especially in the Western world..

From my Christian worldview I perceive this demarcation as a possible, although not requisite, foundation for would be apologists who desire to argue for the mind of man as opposed to the mind of God.  If the mind of man is the creative force providing the imaginative genius and if the genius can only be born from man without the discipline of arbitrary rules one could argue for fine art against existence of God[10] . 

Is such a category of art necessary? 

Such a category is necessary if one accepts the paradigm proposed by Kant in this work.  Accordingly, fine art is not of scientific origin rather is of the imaginative mind of the genius.  Thus, fine art created has no arbitrary rules except that the art must come from the mind of the genius.

What are the criteria for inclusion in or exclusion from this category?

The division of fine arts include “the art of speech, formative art, and the art of the play sensations (as external sense impressions).”[24]  The threshold question for inclusion or exclusion relates to the position of the genius in the equation.  If genius is the originator of the art then fine arts includes this art.  If genius is not the originator then the art is excluded from fine arts.

Is there a theological foundation for “fine arts?”  

This is a most interesting question.  As with all questions the answer “depends” on a number of variables of perspective.  The Christian may have difficulty with the Kantian definition of fine art.  According to Kant fine art originates within the mind of man (the creator) of the artistic expression.  Kant does not appear to offer an alternative to any creative force external to the mind of man.  If art is only created in the mind of man then the question of God is a non sequitur.  For the Christian there is a theological foundation for the fine arts.  That foundation is in the creative force of God instilled in man.  Man was made in the image of God.[1]  I have long held that the “image of God” includes the definition that man has within him the creative force or genius of God.[1]

What is the purpose of fine art?  

According to Kant the purpose of fine art is to advance the culture of the mental powers in the interest of social communication.  This question is answered above in full in the deconstruction of the definition provided by Kant. 

In short, Immanuel Kant’s definition is that fine art is “a mode of representation which is intrinsically purposive, and which, although devoid of an end, has the effect of advancing the culture of the mental powers in the interest of social communication.”[26]

Fine art is (1) a conduit of expression (“a mode of representation”), (2) in possession of innate purpose (“which is intrinsically purposive”),  (3) “devoid of an end”, (4) is for the advancement of the “culture of the mental powers”, (5) that which is “in the interest of social communication”, and (6) inherently of multiple agendas (“and which”) converging into imaginative expression of genius.  These six items reflect Kant’s understanding of the purpose of fine art.

How does this contrast (or perhaps overlap) with the purposes of art that you’d exclude from this category?

Fine art is solely oriented within imaginative genius that leads to the strengthening of the individual and collective mind of society.  Fine art is not defined by arbitrary rules as other forms of art.  Art defined by arbitrary rules may have many definable functions not associated with the fine arts. The comparison of Newton (scientific) and Homer (imaginative) delineates that which is organized by reason and proof as compared to the imaginative.


Footnotes

[1] Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgement (Oxford: Oxford World Classics, 2007), 134.  For purposes of this short essay I have chosen to confine Kant’s work as the primary text.  In particular, section 44 entitled “Fine Arts” (134-135), section 45 entitled “Fine art is an art, so far as it has at the same time the appearance of being nature” (135-136), section 46 entitled “Fine art is the art of genius” (136-137), and section 47 entitled “Elucidation and confirmation of the above explanation of genius” (137-140), 135.

[2] Ibid., 171.

[3] Christopher Dawson, Religion and Culture (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2013), 35.

[4] Ibid., 36.

[5] James V. Schall, The Life of the Mind: On the Joys and Travails of Thinking, 2 ed. (Wilmington, DE. Intercollegiate Studies Institute, 2008), xii.

[6] Ibid., xiii.

[7] Dorothy Sayers, The Lost Tools of Learning and the Mind of the Maker (Paperback) (Oxford, England: Benediction Classics, 2010), 18.

[8] Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality: a Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge (Garden City: Anchor, 1967), 1.

[9] Kant, 134.

[10] Ibid., 134.

[11] Ibid.

[12] Ibid.

[13] Ibid.

[14] Ibid.

[15] Ibid., 136.  Kant says, “fine arts must necessarily be regarded as arts of genius.”  Also, “fine art is only possible as a product of genius” (137).

[16] Ibid., 137.

[17] Ibid.

[18] Ibid., 138.

[19] Ibid.

[20] Ibid.

[21] Ibid.

[22] Ibid., 140.

[23] Ibid.

[24] Ibid., 149.

[25] Gen. 1:27.

[26] Kant, 135.

Bibliography

Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. The Social Construction of Reality: a Treatise

in the Sociology of Knowledge. Garden City: Anchor, 1967.

Dawson, Christopher. Religion and Culture. Washington, D.C.  The Catholic University

of America Press, 2013.

Guyer, Paul. “Kant's Conception of Fine Art.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52,

no. 3 (1994): 275-86.

Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgement. Oxford: Oxford World Classics, 2007.

Sayers, Dorothy. The Lost Tools of Learning and the Mind of the Maker (Paperback).

Oxford, England. Benediction Classics, 2010.

Schall, James V. The Life of the Mind: On the Joys and Travails of Thinking. 2 ed.

Wilmington, DE. Intercollegiate Studies Institute, 2008.

Wicks, Robert. “Kant On Fine Art: Artistic Sublimity Shaped by Beauty.” Journal of

Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53, no. 2 (1995): 189-94.

Share this article
The link has been copied!